語系:
繁體中文
English
說明(常見問題)
回圖書館首頁
手機版館藏查詢
登入
回首頁
切換:
標籤
|
MARC模式
|
ISBD
The Social View of Evidence.
~
Dotan, Ravit.
FindBook
Google Book
Amazon
博客來
The Social View of Evidence.
紀錄類型:
書目-電子資源 : Monograph/item
正題名/作者:
The Social View of Evidence./
作者:
Dotan, Ravit.
出版者:
Ann Arbor : ProQuest Dissertations & Theses, : 2021,
面頁冊數:
71 p.
附註:
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 83-02, Section: B.
Contained By:
Dissertations Abstracts International83-02B.
標題:
Philosophy. -
電子資源:
https://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=28410400
ISBN:
9798535562094
The Social View of Evidence.
Dotan, Ravit.
The Social View of Evidence.
- Ann Arbor : ProQuest Dissertations & Theses, 2021 - 71 p.
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 83-02, Section: B.
Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of California, Berkeley, 2021.
This item must not be sold to any third party vendors.
What makes it the case that something is evidence for a hypothesis? Many people think that evidential relations, e.g., "e is evidence for h", are out there in the world for us to discover. By contrast, I develop a social view of evidence, on which what is evidence for what is decided by groups in the process of social deliberation. Conversations about evidential relations happen everywhere. In science, for example, they take place in peer-reviewed journals, conferences, casual conversations, etc. These conversations are regulated by norms of deliberation, such as norms about which objections are important. The main thesis of my dissertation is that when a social deliberation abides by a set of these norms, the conclusions that emerge have epistemic implications for those who accept them. For example, at some point the scientific community concluded that red spots are evidence for measles. To the extent that their deliberative process satisfied the scientific norms of deliberation, red spots became evidence for measles for those who accept these norms. I support the social view of evidence by showing that it is fruitful: it explains key phenomena related to evidence. One of them is the phenomenon of resistance to evidence. We know this phenomenon from the public sphere, as politicians and members of the public resist evidence on climate change, vaccines, and so on. We also know this phenomenon from feminist science, as feminist scientists push back against long-standing consensuses in medicine, anthropology, and other fields. The social view explains how resistance to evidence works and distinguishes epistemically good from epistemically bad cases of resistance, which other accounts of evidence cannot do. To explain resistance, I use the fact that individuals can hypothesize about evidence by thinking through whether the claim "e is evidence for h" would survive the right kind of social deliberation, e.g., by running objections and responses in their heads. Resistance occurs when individuals favor their hypothetical over the outcome of social deliberation. We mark resistance as epistemically good when the hypothetical conforms to our norms of deliberation to a high degree, e.g., when the resisting agent can respond to dialectical moves in permissible ways. Feminist scientists are well-positioned to conform to the scientific norms to a high degree given their training. Laypersons, such as some anti-vaxxers, are often ill-positioned. If these anti-vaxxers accept the scientific norms of deliberation, which they seem to be if they accept some scientific evidence, then their denial violates even their own norms.An implication of the social view, which I develop, is that evidence is political. The reasons is that the norms of deliberation are political. For example, scientists used to test medication only on men. This inclination reflects norms of deliberation which deprioritize objections about women's health and are tied to women's political status. More generally, prioritization of objections depends on what the group values, which is influenced by the power structures in and around the group.You might wonder whether some norms of deliberation are universally better than others no matter what the priorities of the group are. I explore a theorem from machine learning, called the "No Free Lunch Theorem" (NFL), which suggests otherwise. According to NFL, no learning algorithm universally gives more accurate predictions than any other. Rather, an algorithm can outperform another only if we restrict the set of problems we are trying to solve. Since social deliberation can be thought of as an algorithm, this implies that no form of social deliberation universally gives more accurate predictions. Rather, one form of social deliberation can outperform another only if we restrict the set of problems of interest. I use NFL to bring out non-epistemic aspects of accuracy and other measures of goodness of theories, which helps let go of the (misleading) intuition that data can be used to choose between theories in purely epistemic ways. To conclude, the social view of evidence holds that what is evidence for what is determined by social deliberation and it explains many key features of evidence. The view implies that different groups may give rise to different evidential relations and that the difference may be due to differences in what they value. Although this implication may seem surprising, it is supported by NFL, which entails that there is no way to choose between the norms of these different groups based on accuracy alone.
ISBN: 9798535562094Subjects--Topical Terms:
516511
Philosophy.
The Social View of Evidence.
LDR
:05639nmm a2200349 4500
001
2284882
005
20211124093245.5
008
220723s2021 ||||||||||||||||| ||eng d
020
$a
9798535562094
035
$a
(MiAaPQ)AAI28410400
035
$a
AAI28410400
040
$a
MiAaPQ
$c
MiAaPQ
100
1
$a
Dotan, Ravit.
$3
3564085
245
1 4
$a
The Social View of Evidence.
260
1
$a
Ann Arbor :
$b
ProQuest Dissertations & Theses,
$c
2021
300
$a
71 p.
500
$a
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 83-02, Section: B.
500
$a
Advisor: Dasgupta, Shamik;Buchak, Lara.
502
$a
Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of California, Berkeley, 2021.
506
$a
This item must not be sold to any third party vendors.
520
$a
What makes it the case that something is evidence for a hypothesis? Many people think that evidential relations, e.g., "e is evidence for h", are out there in the world for us to discover. By contrast, I develop a social view of evidence, on which what is evidence for what is decided by groups in the process of social deliberation. Conversations about evidential relations happen everywhere. In science, for example, they take place in peer-reviewed journals, conferences, casual conversations, etc. These conversations are regulated by norms of deliberation, such as norms about which objections are important. The main thesis of my dissertation is that when a social deliberation abides by a set of these norms, the conclusions that emerge have epistemic implications for those who accept them. For example, at some point the scientific community concluded that red spots are evidence for measles. To the extent that their deliberative process satisfied the scientific norms of deliberation, red spots became evidence for measles for those who accept these norms. I support the social view of evidence by showing that it is fruitful: it explains key phenomena related to evidence. One of them is the phenomenon of resistance to evidence. We know this phenomenon from the public sphere, as politicians and members of the public resist evidence on climate change, vaccines, and so on. We also know this phenomenon from feminist science, as feminist scientists push back against long-standing consensuses in medicine, anthropology, and other fields. The social view explains how resistance to evidence works and distinguishes epistemically good from epistemically bad cases of resistance, which other accounts of evidence cannot do. To explain resistance, I use the fact that individuals can hypothesize about evidence by thinking through whether the claim "e is evidence for h" would survive the right kind of social deliberation, e.g., by running objections and responses in their heads. Resistance occurs when individuals favor their hypothetical over the outcome of social deliberation. We mark resistance as epistemically good when the hypothetical conforms to our norms of deliberation to a high degree, e.g., when the resisting agent can respond to dialectical moves in permissible ways. Feminist scientists are well-positioned to conform to the scientific norms to a high degree given their training. Laypersons, such as some anti-vaxxers, are often ill-positioned. If these anti-vaxxers accept the scientific norms of deliberation, which they seem to be if they accept some scientific evidence, then their denial violates even their own norms.An implication of the social view, which I develop, is that evidence is political. The reasons is that the norms of deliberation are political. For example, scientists used to test medication only on men. This inclination reflects norms of deliberation which deprioritize objections about women's health and are tied to women's political status. More generally, prioritization of objections depends on what the group values, which is influenced by the power structures in and around the group.You might wonder whether some norms of deliberation are universally better than others no matter what the priorities of the group are. I explore a theorem from machine learning, called the "No Free Lunch Theorem" (NFL), which suggests otherwise. According to NFL, no learning algorithm universally gives more accurate predictions than any other. Rather, an algorithm can outperform another only if we restrict the set of problems we are trying to solve. Since social deliberation can be thought of as an algorithm, this implies that no form of social deliberation universally gives more accurate predictions. Rather, one form of social deliberation can outperform another only if we restrict the set of problems of interest. I use NFL to bring out non-epistemic aspects of accuracy and other measures of goodness of theories, which helps let go of the (misleading) intuition that data can be used to choose between theories in purely epistemic ways. To conclude, the social view of evidence holds that what is evidence for what is determined by social deliberation and it explains many key features of evidence. The view implies that different groups may give rise to different evidential relations and that the difference may be due to differences in what they value. Although this implication may seem surprising, it is supported by NFL, which entails that there is no way to choose between the norms of these different groups based on accuracy alone.
590
$a
School code: 0028.
650
4
$a
Philosophy.
$3
516511
650
4
$a
Epistemology.
$3
896969
650
4
$a
Philosophy of science.
$2
bicssc
$3
2079849
650
4
$a
Skepticism.
$3
564682
650
4
$a
Standards.
$3
3560310
650
4
$a
Vaccines.
$3
684854
650
4
$a
Accuracy.
$3
3559958
650
4
$a
Scientists.
$3
531895
650
4
$a
Astronomy.
$3
517668
650
4
$a
Debates.
$3
3564086
650
4
$a
Puzzles.
$3
530766
650
4
$a
Community.
$3
531337
650
4
$a
Mechanics.
$3
525881
650
4
$a
Climate change.
$2
bicssc
$3
2079509
650
4
$a
Feminism.
$3
526785
650
4
$a
Testimony.
$3
3563395
650
4
$a
Hypotheses.
$3
3560118
650
4
$a
Measles.
$3
3564087
650
4
$a
Good & evil.
$3
3564088
650
4
$a
Algorithms.
$3
536374
650
4
$a
Mercury.
$3
3564089
650
4
$a
Norms.
$3
3562802
650
4
$a
Sexual orientation discrimination.
$3
3564090
650
4
$a
Judges & magistrates.
$3
3562075
690
$a
0422
690
$a
0393
690
$a
0402
690
$a
0346
690
$a
0404
690
$a
0606
710
2
$a
University of California, Berkeley.
$b
Philosophy.
$3
1683966
773
0
$t
Dissertations Abstracts International
$g
83-02B.
790
$a
0028
791
$a
Ph.D.
792
$a
2021
793
$a
English
856
4 0
$u
https://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=28410400
筆 0 讀者評論
館藏地:
全部
電子資源
出版年:
卷號:
館藏
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
條碼號
典藏地名稱
館藏流通類別
資料類型
索書號
使用類型
借閱狀態
預約狀態
備註欄
附件
W9436615
電子資源
11.線上閱覽_V
電子書
EB
一般使用(Normal)
在架
0
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
多媒體
評論
新增評論
分享你的心得
Export
取書館
處理中
...
變更密碼
登入