語系:
繁體中文
English
說明(常見問題)
回圖書館首頁
手機版館藏查詢
登入
回首頁
切換:
標籤
|
MARC模式
|
ISBD
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide bet...
~
Helton, Grace.
FindBook
Google Book
Amazon
博客來
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief.
紀錄類型:
書目-電子資源 : Monograph/item
正題名/作者:
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief./
作者:
Helton, Grace.
出版者:
Ann Arbor : ProQuest Dissertations & Theses, : 2015,
面頁冊數:
139 p.
附註:
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 77-03, Section: A.
Contained By:
Dissertations Abstracts International77-03A.
標題:
Philosophy of Science. -
電子資源:
http://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=3716531
ISBN:
9781321954197
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief.
Helton, Grace.
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief.
- Ann Arbor : ProQuest Dissertations & Theses, 2015 - 139 p.
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 77-03, Section: A.
Thesis (Ph.D.)--New York University, 2015.
This item is not available from ProQuest Dissertations & Theses.
On one traditional view, perception and belief are distinguished by their rational roles. On this view, belief is characteristically formed by and revised in accordance with available evidence, whereas perception is formed and extinguished exclusively in response to modality-specific sensory inputs. Both aspects of this view face serious challenges from recent empirical and conceptual developments. On the belief side of things, there is now evidence that many judgments are formed quickly, automatically, and heuristically, and not obviously in response to evidence. There is also evidence that some judgments persevere despite evidence against them, for instance, when their subject is motivated to maintain those judgments. In my dissertation, I argue for a particular strategy of distinguishing belief and perception by their respective rational roles. In particular, I claim that all beliefs, insofar as they are beliefs, have a nomic capacity to be rationally revised in response to any bit of available, sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with them. In contrast, at least some perceptual experiences lack a nomic capacity to be rationally revised in response to any bit of relevant evidence. I further argue that the proposed recasting of the belief-perception divide can help settle a currently disputed issue in the philosophy of perception, that of which kinds of features we can perceive. The dissertation is structured as a series of thematically connected but self-standing essays. In the first essay, 'The Revisability View of Belief,' I argue for the view that all beliefs are nomically capable of being rationally revised in response to any bit of sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with them. I claim that this view follows from the conjunction of two independently plausible principles: first, that subjects who enjoy some belief at the same time that they enjoy sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with that belief are prima facie rationally required to revise that belief. Second, that if some subject is prima facie rationally required to revise some mental state, then that subject is nomically, and more particularly, psychologically capable of revising that mental state. In the second essay, 'How Not to Argue for High-level Perception,' I transition to the issue of what kinds of features we can perceive. On one view, we can only perceive so-called low-level features; with respect to visual experience, paradigmatic low-level features are shape, color, and movement. On another view, we can additionally perceive a range of high-level features, such as artifactual features, causal features, and social features. I consider and reject three extant strategies of arguing in favor of the view that we perceive high-level features: introspective arguments, veridicality arguments, and phenomenal contrast argu-ments. In the third and final essay, 'Visually Perceiving the Intentions of Others,' I put the view of belief developed in Essay 1 to work as part of an argument that we can visually perceive at least some kinds of high-level features. In particular, we sometimes visually perceive the intentions of others. I begin by considering the mental state of the typical subject viewing an animation of two shapes moving away from a third shape, in an apparent fleeing motion. This mental state represents the shapes as fleeing, and we know that this experience is: reliably elicitable in most subjects, cross-culturally stable, and diachronically stable. Nevertheless, most subjects know that the shapes aren't really fleeing; since they know the shapes to be inanimate entities that can neither self-propel nor act on a proximal intention of evasion, both of which are required for fleeing. On the best explanation, the reason subjects' mental state as of the shapes fleeing persists despite the evidence against it is that the mental state lacks a nomic capacity to be rationally revised. If we accept the view that all beliefs must be nomically capable of being rationally revised, the mental state as of fleeing cannot be a belief. On the next best explanation, that mental state is a visual experience. Thus, just as we can see something as blue or as moving to the right, so too can we see someone as intending to evade someone else. (Abstract shortened by UMI.).
ISBN: 9781321954197Subjects--Topical Terms:
894954
Philosophy of Science.
Subjects--Index Terms:
Belief
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief.
LDR
:05689nmm a2200409 4500
001
2267702
005
20200724103041.5
008
220629s2015 ||||||||||||||||| ||eng d
020
$a
9781321954197
035
$a
(MiAaPQ)AAI3716531
035
$a
(MiAaPQ)nyu:12218
035
$a
AAI3716531
040
$a
MiAaPQ
$c
MiAaPQ
100
1
$a
Helton, Grace.
$3
3544965
245
1 0
$a
Two Worlds, One Mind: The Divide between Perception and Belief.
260
1
$a
Ann Arbor :
$b
ProQuest Dissertations & Theses,
$c
2015
300
$a
139 p.
500
$a
Source: Dissertations Abstracts International, Volume: 77-03, Section: A.
500
$a
Publisher info.: Dissertation/Thesis.
500
$a
Advisor: Block, Ned.
502
$a
Thesis (Ph.D.)--New York University, 2015.
506
$a
This item is not available from ProQuest Dissertations & Theses.
506
$a
This item must not be added to any third party search indexes.
506
$a
This item must not be sold to any third party vendors.
520
$a
On one traditional view, perception and belief are distinguished by their rational roles. On this view, belief is characteristically formed by and revised in accordance with available evidence, whereas perception is formed and extinguished exclusively in response to modality-specific sensory inputs. Both aspects of this view face serious challenges from recent empirical and conceptual developments. On the belief side of things, there is now evidence that many judgments are formed quickly, automatically, and heuristically, and not obviously in response to evidence. There is also evidence that some judgments persevere despite evidence against them, for instance, when their subject is motivated to maintain those judgments. In my dissertation, I argue for a particular strategy of distinguishing belief and perception by their respective rational roles. In particular, I claim that all beliefs, insofar as they are beliefs, have a nomic capacity to be rationally revised in response to any bit of available, sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with them. In contrast, at least some perceptual experiences lack a nomic capacity to be rationally revised in response to any bit of relevant evidence. I further argue that the proposed recasting of the belief-perception divide can help settle a currently disputed issue in the philosophy of perception, that of which kinds of features we can perceive. The dissertation is structured as a series of thematically connected but self-standing essays. In the first essay, 'The Revisability View of Belief,' I argue for the view that all beliefs are nomically capable of being rationally revised in response to any bit of sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with them. I claim that this view follows from the conjunction of two independently plausible principles: first, that subjects who enjoy some belief at the same time that they enjoy sufficiently strong evidence that conflicts with that belief are prima facie rationally required to revise that belief. Second, that if some subject is prima facie rationally required to revise some mental state, then that subject is nomically, and more particularly, psychologically capable of revising that mental state. In the second essay, 'How Not to Argue for High-level Perception,' I transition to the issue of what kinds of features we can perceive. On one view, we can only perceive so-called low-level features; with respect to visual experience, paradigmatic low-level features are shape, color, and movement. On another view, we can additionally perceive a range of high-level features, such as artifactual features, causal features, and social features. I consider and reject three extant strategies of arguing in favor of the view that we perceive high-level features: introspective arguments, veridicality arguments, and phenomenal contrast argu-ments. In the third and final essay, 'Visually Perceiving the Intentions of Others,' I put the view of belief developed in Essay 1 to work as part of an argument that we can visually perceive at least some kinds of high-level features. In particular, we sometimes visually perceive the intentions of others. I begin by considering the mental state of the typical subject viewing an animation of two shapes moving away from a third shape, in an apparent fleeing motion. This mental state represents the shapes as fleeing, and we know that this experience is: reliably elicitable in most subjects, cross-culturally stable, and diachronically stable. Nevertheless, most subjects know that the shapes aren't really fleeing; since they know the shapes to be inanimate entities that can neither self-propel nor act on a proximal intention of evasion, both of which are required for fleeing. On the best explanation, the reason subjects' mental state as of the shapes fleeing persists despite the evidence against it is that the mental state lacks a nomic capacity to be rationally revised. If we accept the view that all beliefs must be nomically capable of being rationally revised, the mental state as of fleeing cannot be a belief. On the next best explanation, that mental state is a visual experience. Thus, just as we can see something as blue or as moving to the right, so too can we see someone as intending to evade someone else. (Abstract shortened by UMI.).
590
$a
School code: 0146.
650
4
$a
Philosophy of Science.
$3
894954
650
4
$a
Philosophy.
$3
516511
653
$a
Belief
653
$a
Delusions
653
$a
Dual-systems theory
653
$a
Evidence-responsiveness
653
$a
Perception
690
$a
0402
690
$a
0422
710
2
$a
New York University.
$b
Philosophy.
$3
1031970
773
0
$t
Dissertations Abstracts International
$g
77-03A.
790
$a
0146
791
$a
Ph.D.
792
$a
2015
793
$a
English
856
4 0
$u
http://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=3716531
筆 0 讀者評論
館藏地:
全部
電子資源
出版年:
卷號:
館藏
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
條碼號
典藏地名稱
館藏流通類別
資料類型
索書號
使用類型
借閱狀態
預約狀態
備註欄
附件
W9419936
電子資源
11.線上閱覽_V
電子書
EB
一般使用(Normal)
在架
0
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
多媒體
評論
新增評論
分享你的心得
Export
取書館
處理中
...
變更密碼
登入