語系:
繁體中文
English
說明(常見問題)
回圖書館首頁
手機版館藏查詢
登入
回首頁
切換:
標籤
|
MARC模式
|
ISBD
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
~
Ward, Thomas Michael.
FindBook
Google Book
Amazon
博客來
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
紀錄類型:
書目-電子資源 : Monograph/item
正題名/作者:
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus./
作者:
Ward, Thomas Michael.
面頁冊數:
213 p.
附註:
Source: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 73-03, Section: A, page: 1048.
Contained By:
Dissertation Abstracts International73-03A.
標題:
Philosophy. -
電子資源:
http://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=3486547
ISBN:
9781267050137
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
Ward, Thomas Michael.
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
- 213 p.
Source: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 73-03, Section: A, page: 1048.
Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of California, Los Angeles, 2011.
Hylomorphism is a metaphysical theory that seeks to posit some entity, form (morphe), whose theoretical role it is to shape or organize matter ( hyle). For two or more objects to be similar in kind is for them to share the same kind of form. For an object to pass out of existence is for its matter to cease to be formed by its form, and for an object to come into existence is for some matter to become newly formed. This dissertation examines several features of John Duns Scotus's version of hylomorphism.
ISBN: 9781267050137Subjects--Topical Terms:
516511
Philosophy.
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
LDR
:05568nmm a2200337 4500
001
2064062
005
20151109121407.5
008
170521s2011 ||||||||||||||||| ||eng d
020
$a
9781267050137
035
$a
(MiAaPQ)AAI3486547
035
$a
AAI3486547
040
$a
MiAaPQ
$c
MiAaPQ
100
1
$a
Ward, Thomas Michael.
$3
3178617
245
1 4
$a
The Hylomorphism of John Duns Scotus.
300
$a
213 p.
500
$a
Source: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 73-03, Section: A, page: 1048.
500
$a
Adviser: Calvin G. Normore.
502
$a
Thesis (Ph.D.)--University of California, Los Angeles, 2011.
520
$a
Hylomorphism is a metaphysical theory that seeks to posit some entity, form (morphe), whose theoretical role it is to shape or organize matter ( hyle). For two or more objects to be similar in kind is for them to share the same kind of form. For an object to pass out of existence is for its matter to cease to be formed by its form, and for an object to come into existence is for some matter to become newly formed. This dissertation examines several features of John Duns Scotus's version of hylomorphism.
520
$a
Chapter 1 provides some philosophical background to Scotus's hylomorphism, with a special focus on Scotus's theory of matter. Scotus is committed to prime matter, an actual entity, really distinct from form, persisting through change, whose nature is simply to be a passive power for change. I argue that for Scotus matter's being a passive power does not entail that it persists through change.
520
$a
Chapter 2 analyzes Scotus's account of how matter and form become parts. Scotus thinks that a form is a part of any object whose form it is, and therefore form cannot be offered as a general explanation of how things become parts. Each of matter and form can exist on its own (if only by divine power) but not compose a substance. Since, in general, changes in relative properties must be explained by changes in absolute (non-relative) properties, for a thing to become a part---to acquire a parthood relation---some absolute change must occur. Scotus argues that the only absolute change that can explain how matter and form acquire parthood relations is the production of a substance. Developing the Aristotelian idea that matter and form exercise certain kinds of causality, Scotus argues that matter and form are the causes of the substance they compose, and identifies the parthood relations of matter and form with their causal relations toward substance.
520
$a
Chapter 3 is the first philosophical exploration of a little known feature of Scotus's hylomorphism: Scotus held that the extended parts of some material substance, such as the eyes and hands of Socrates, are themselves substances, with their own specific substantial forms. I argue that Scotus thinks that the form of corporeity is nothing over and above the forms of the plurality of extended parts. I develop an alternate account according to which a plurality of substances potentially compose a substance when they are essentially ordered to one another in the order of final- and efficient-causality. I close the chapter with some reflections on Scotus's reasons for denying that the plurality of all the substances compose one world-substance/.
520
$a
Chapter 4 considers Scotus's reasons for denying that the four chemical elements actually exist in the bodies of which they are the basic ingredients. Scotus and most medieval philosophers were agreed that the elements cease to exist when they are mixed. I argue that Scotus's fundamental reason for holding the majority view is that elemental bodies cannot compose a unity of order: they are neither efficient nor final-causally related to one another, since elements act for the sake of reaching their proper sublunary region, and they naturally corrupt elemental bodies of other kinds if they are able. Any combination of elemental bodies therefore lacks the unity requisite for a plurality of substances potentially to compose a complex substance.
520
$a
The final chapter applies the results of the preceding chapters to show how Scotus would respond to a problem with the application of hylomorphism to living things. First, hylomorphism seems to entail that matter is contingently formed by its form. Second, the principle of homonymy, endorsed by Aristotle and Aquinas, holds that some substance, s, is a member of a kind, K, if and only if it is able to perform the characteristic function or functions of the Ks. By the first thesis, Socrates's corpse is numerically identical with Socrates's body, since Aristotle identifies Socrates's body as the matter of Socrates. By the second thesis, Socrates's corpse is not numerically identical with Socrates's body, since the corpse cannot perform the characteristic functions of a human body. This contradiction has been called "the fundamental problem about hylomorphism." I argue that Scotus's pluralism about substantial forms entails rejection of the homonymy principle, since at least some organic parts, such as hands, eyes, and kidneys, are distinct kinds of substances, which depend on an organism only for their natural operations and not for their existence. Therefore Scotus's hylomorphism solves the fundamental problem. (Abstract shortened by UMI.).
590
$a
School code: 0031.
650
4
$a
Philosophy.
$3
516511
650
4
$a
Metaphysics.
$3
517082
690
$a
0422
690
$a
0396
710
2
$a
University of California, Los Angeles.
$3
626622
773
0
$t
Dissertation Abstracts International
$g
73-03A.
790
$a
0031
791
$a
Ph.D.
792
$a
2011
793
$a
English
856
4 0
$u
http://pqdd.sinica.edu.tw/twdaoapp/servlet/advanced?query=3486547
筆 0 讀者評論
館藏地:
全部
電子資源
出版年:
卷號:
館藏
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
條碼號
典藏地名稱
館藏流通類別
資料類型
索書號
使用類型
借閱狀態
預約狀態
備註欄
附件
W9296720
電子資源
11.線上閱覽_V
電子書
EB
一般使用(Normal)
在架
0
1 筆 • 頁數 1 •
1
多媒體
評論
新增評論
分享你的心得
Export
取書館
處理中
...
變更密碼
登入